Self and
Knowledge
M.A. Muqtedar Khan
Managing Editor, AJISS
General Secretary
Association of Muslim Social Scientists
The contemporary intellectual revival of Muslim societies
proposes a profound but problematic relationship between identity and
epistemology, and between self and knowledge. I propose to elucidate this
relationship and its implications by making a fundamental distinction
between self and identity, and showing how there can be many identities but
only one self. I begin by inquiring into the meaning of identity symbols
such as "Islam" or "Muslim" prior to knowledge. For
example, what is the meaning and relationship between identity and knowledge
in Islamization of knowledge or Islamic Philosophy? In both types of
knowledge, identity is prior to knowledge in an epistemological, and well as
an ontological sense.
Ontologically we are suggesting that the existence of
Islamic psychology or Islamic philosophy is contingent on the being of an
agency such as Islam or Muslims. Epistemologically, we are arguing that
Islam includes a theory of knowledge, and Islamic principles constitute
paradigmatic values from which Islamic psychology or Islamic philosophy can
be derived. Clearly, the prefix Islamic gives an identity to knowledge. In
other words, there are certain truth claims which derive their legitimacy
not because their truth is self-evident or rationally deducible or
empirically verifiable, but because they satisfy certain criteria which
establishes their identity as Islamic.
The issue of criteria that determine what constitutes
knowledge (epistemology) is indeed crucial. The first thing that needs to be
resolved is whether these criteria are universally intelligible or are
functions of culture/identity and value systems. I would like to posit that
in the realms of determining the validity of socially meaningful practices
it is possible to have relativistic criteria for determining the
validity of social truths. Knowledge about answers to questions such as Is
polygyny or homosexuality acceptable? or Are religious rights more important
than economic rights? may be determined based on criteria that are located
within the corpus of tradition and ethos of a given cultural milieu. This is
accommodation of cultural pluralism. But in the realms of science and
philosophy, reasoning and empirical evidence alone can be the criteria for
determining the merit of knowledge claims. If we stray from this position,
and succumb to the postmodern seduction of treating all knowledge claims as
identity narratives, then there will be no science, no philosophy, and no
Truth. There will be nothing universally intelligible. Even God will become
a culture artifact. The Truth of a universal God necessitates the existence
of certain universal intelligibles, to the understanding of which science
and philosophy are dedicated.
Many Muslim thinkers reject the proposition that
knowledge about things in this world can be produced through reason and/or
empirical observations alone and seek a missing Islamic ingredient that
would interact with observed data and reason to produce Islamic knowledge
whose veracity would be beyond doubt. I think this claim is based on reason
and/or observation. And since the current outcome of this knowledge is an
immoral West, Muslim thinkers tend to reject reason and observation as sole
criteria of determining the merit of knowledge claims, and search for some
magical Islamic ingredient that would sanitize (Islamize) reason and
observation.
We must recognize that where reason and observation
rule as in natural science, the West does produce significant results. But
when it comes to political, social, economic, and moral issues, the many
failures of the present West are a testimony to the fact that its triumphs
in the natural sciences are not replicated in the social sciences. It is
my conviction that such is the case because in the social arena, Western
scholars too allow their identity (based on secular humanism and
anthropocentrism) to corrupt their understanding. They allow their
politics to implicate their social sciences. Therefore, we must be very
careful before we allow Western discourses the claim that they are based
purely on reason and/or observation.
Consider for a moment the methodology of the Qur'an. It
does not ask us to believe in itself or in God because it says so. The
Qur'an is full of exhortations to think and reflect upon the signs of God
in text as well as in nature. It asks us to look at the planets and
reflect upon their laws of motion. It recommends that we know God and
understand his laws through observation of the order in nature. The Qur'an
demands that we use our 'aql (reason/intellect) to reach the truth. It
also expects us to infer lessons from history and from the experiences of
civilizations that preceded us (Ilm-ul-Sunan). In some places God
challenges us to bring forward proof if we disagree with him. The mood in
the Qur'an is completely scientific and deeply amenable to the idea of
Truth as verifiable and intelligible through reason and observation. The
Muslim faith is not a belief in things unintelligible to reason or
science. It is a faith, which is more like considered judgment. Indeed, it
would be un-Qr'anic to underestimate the importance of reason and
observation in knowledge. A Muslim is not just a believing being but also
a knowing being. Indeed, the "belief" is a function of
knowledge.
Let us now return to Islamic social science and Islamic
philosophy. When we use identity symbols prior to knowledge, are we
stating that these types of knowledge are not subject to universal
verification? Is external verification of any type, empirical or rational
is not the criteria for determining the merit of knowledge claims, then
does not knowledge become ideology? It is like saying that in order to see
the truth in Islamic philosophy or Islamic psychology you must believe in
Islam. What then is the difference between philosophy and theology or
social science and theology?
Before we explore the relationship between identity and
knowledge let us scrutinize the idea of identity itself. Identity is, in
many ways, our direct or mediated understanding of who we are. Who we are
can be understood in individual as well as collective terms. When we
indicate to ourselves who we are, and this is usually accomplished by
attributing to ourselves meanings that give us "distinction of
worth," we are creating a self-identity. When we indicate to others
who we are, this is usually accomplished by emphasizing difference,
we create a strategic identity. When we indicate ourselves to others but
seek to emphasize commonality (identity) and not difference,
we create collective identities.
There are at least three levels at which identity is
understood in the discussion above. Self-identity results when the subject
and object are identical. This is knowledge of who we are that is
unmediated by strategic context and other existing identities. While all
other forms of identities are constructed, self-identity is essential.
Thus, when a person claims to be an Indian-American-Sunni-Hanafi Muslim,
the person claims to owe allegiance to multiple identities. This person
may also choose to be only an Indian, or only an American, or only a
Muslim. Indeed, under various circumstances the person may consciously
choose to emphasize one identity over another. Nevertheless, whatever
identity the person may choose to identify with at any given time, his or
her self-knowledge remains unchanged. Thus, regardless of what the person
chooses to introduce him or herself as, the person's
"self-identity", the "I" that speaks to the I is the
same.
All other identities are really strategic, contextual,
and contingent. They are dependent on the "other" in contrast to
whom the self is defined. For example, let us consider the following
identities. An Arab essentially means that the subject is not a Persian or
a European or anything else (ajami). When an Arab-Christian says he
is an Arab-Christian he is choosing to particularly distinguish himself
from Arab-Muslims. Thus, when one asserts self-identity, one
simultaneously distances oneself from "other" identities. The
construction of identity is a consequence of emphasizing difference.
Collective identities are the result of the opposite process. Collective
identities undermine difference and emphasize identity.
These types of identities are instrumental and
strategic because they are a function of how the other is perceived or
positioned. For example, if an Arab Christian seeks to identify with a
European Christian, he emphasizes identity and suggests, "We are both
Christians," to express collective identity. If, however, he
chooses to distance himself from the European Christian, he emphasizes difference
and says, "I am an Arab and the other is not."
Based upon the above discussion, I would like to argue
that, while we are capable of possessing multiple identities, we have only
one self--the "I" that I am always aware of, no matter what
identity I choose to deploy in a given sociopolitical context. From the
discussion above we have also learned that identities are defined in
contrast to others. But how is self defined? The essential self, that
which is distinct from constructed identities, the "I" that one
refers to in knowledge of the self, is recognized in opposition to God who
is the other in this equation. I think that when I assert "I," I
am basically stating that I am not God. Thus in a very profound sense, the
assertion of the primordial self is the accomplishment of two acts of
truth. When we claim that I exist and I have a self, I am actually
asserting that I am not God, and that there is a God/Creator whose
creation I am. Since God is eternal, unchanging and absolute, the self
that is posited in contradistinction to God is also eternal, unchanging
and absolute. In a beautiful way the relationship between the self and its
creator at once includes identity as well as difference. To
assert that the self cannot exist without the other (God) is the
profoundest expression of identity, but to recognize that the self
and the other belong to different ontological categories, creator and
created, is to recognize a profound and unparalleled difference.
The postmodern dilemma of order in a world of multiple
identities is resolvable by recognizing that while there are many
identities, there is only one self. Identities are constructed through
historical and cultural signifiers of meaning, with symbols and through
shared values. Identities are always contextual, constructed, and
relative. But the self is absolute, essential, and eternal. Identities are
a product of "horizontal relationships" of identity and difference,
and the self is the consequence of a "vertical relationship,"
which simultaneously posits identity as well as difference.
Multiple identities are possible because multiple others are possible.
There are, in a manner of speaking, as many identities as there are
relationships between self and other. But only one self is possible
because there is only one other (God). The primordial self is the
humanized reflection of the exclusive singularity of God. Since there is
only one God, there can be only one other in the vertical dimension and
therefore only one true self. Therefore, in the horizontal realm I can be
Muslim, sunni, younger, liberal, and many more; in the vertical sense, I
can only be 'abd Allah ('abd is the opposite of God usually
translated as servant or slave.)
Having discussed the distinctions between the divinely
constituted identities, I now propose to explore the relationship between
knowledge and self/identity. Let us, for example consider the claim
advanced by many philosophers, particularly Dr. Seyyed Hossein Nasr, that
there is such a thing as Islamic philosophy. This claim places identity
prior to philosophy. It is not a product of philosophy. For to claim an
Islamic philosophy, is to assert the existence of an Islamic self which
philosophizes without implicating the self (current discourses on
Islamization of thought do not distinguish between self and identity as I
have in this discussion). That is, self and philosophy are forever
separated. Now we are forced to conceptualize self-reflection and
reflection as two mutually exclusive processes. If the self is not a
product of philosophical reflection then what is self-reflection? We are
forced to imagine a metaphilosophy of the self, prior to Islamic
philosophy.
Thus when knowledge is a function of a self or an
identity and the process of knowing does not implicate the self or the
identity itself, then we have a knowledge form that is subordinate to the
self/identity. This is not knowledge of things as they are but is
knowledge of things as they relate to the self or identity. An excellent
example of this type of knowledge is the knowledge of Islam that is
produced in the West by orientalists. The orientalists' discourse is not
knowledge about Islam as it is. It is knowledge of Islam as it relates to
the West. This discourse in understanding Islam seeks to realize Western
identity and its interests while protecting it from potential influence
from Islam.
Similarly, when we advance knowledge forms such as
Islamic psychology or Islamic philosophy, these discourses primarily
defend the self/identity of Islam rather than understand things as they
are. It is quite possible that our knowledge of things may reshape our
understanding of our self/identity. For if the West were to understand
Islam as it is then it would simultaneously change their understanding of
who they are. The most obvious change that I can envision is that the West
would think of itself as an Abrahamic civilization rather than a
Judeo-Christian one if its knowledge of Islam were more than strategic.
The fear that knowledge, unsubordinated to identity, will transform us,
compels us to advance discourses such as Islamic philosophy or Islamic
psychology. We are guarding who we are when we think, and therefore our
thoughts are limited by our conceptions of ourselves.
I believe that if we allow our identity, which is
horizontally constituted with respects to "others" (such as the
West) to shape our discourses, then the knowledge we produce will only
serve the purpose of defending our identity. The constant critique of
Western discourses and the unceasing desire to distinguish between Western
and Islamic social sciences or between Western and Islamic philosophies,
is basically as manifestation of our politics--to maintain the difference
between them and us. And because identities are imaginary, knowledge
emerging from these identities too is imaginary.
But while identities are imaginary, the self is real
and unchanging because it emerges and derives its meanings from the
absolute. Knowledge, which is produced to defend this self, will like it
to be real. In conclusion, since what we know is so profoundly linked with
who we are, we better know who we are in order that we may know. We must
be very careful to separate our identities from our self, for identities
not only corrupt our self but also influence what we can know. We can run
the risk of allowing our identities to impact our politics but we must not
allow them to implicate our epistemology.
We must learn to eschew the influence of identities and
search for knowledge based upon an understanding of the primordial self.
This knowledge is in many ways the knowledge that speaks about the nature
of the divine and the nature of the self and the relationship between the
two. It is a product of the interaction of our 'aql (reason/intellection)
with revelation and nature. It is like simultaneously reading two books
(revealed and created) authored by the divine being. Both are mere
accumulation of His ayahs (signs). Indeed, the keys to
understanding the secrets of one book may be found in the other. The
simultaneous reading will open more locks to the truth than one can
imagine. The knowledge that will emerge from this simultaneous reading is
the knowledge that we seek in endeavors like Islamic philosophy and
Islamic social science. A knowledge that is grounded in the recognition of
the primordial self.
What does this relationship between self and knowledge
mean to the intellectual revival of the Islamic civilization? First of
all, it deconstructs the very idea of Islamic civilization as we
understand it today. Islamic civilization as we understand it was not an
intended consequence of a systematic methodology. Nor was it premised on a
given Islamic science or Islamic epistemology. It slowly emerged through a
historical process, which was a consequence of a people's struggle to
realize the meaning of their self in social context. What we call Islamic
civilization today got its identity much after Islam's decline. In its own
time it was a manifestation of itself. The present discussion begs the
question of whether the primordial self exists only in the individual
state or also in the collective form? We shall defer that discussion for
another occasion. However, at the moment we must keep in mind that the
idea of a collective self is essential to any discussion of an Islamic or
any other civilization.
Finally, I would like to suggest that our efforts to
reconstruct a glorious Islamic civilization should not be premised upon
our understanding of its identity in history. We must on the contrary
discover it inside us, in the meaning of self. Therefore, we must
reestablish our connection with the divine and enable the vertical
constitution of the self. We must escape the confines of our horizontal
relationships to free knowledge from ideology, and epistemology from
identity. Only then will a civilization emerge that will embody the
Qur'anic verse, nurun 'ala nur (light upon light), to which the
identity, Islamic civilization, maybe appropriately attributed.
This Article was taken from "The
American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences", Fall 1999 issue.
|