| |
The second reason of importance in the large-scale inclination towards
materialism in the West lies in the inadequacy of its philosophical ideas. In fact, that
which is called 'divine philosophy' (hikmat-e ilahi) is in a very backward state in the
West, though perhaps some people may not concede that the West has not reached the level
of the divine philosophy of the East, especially Islamic philosophy.
Many philosophical ideas which raise a hue and cry in Europe are among
the elementary issues of Islamic philosophy. In translations of Western philosophical
works we come across certain ridiculous observations cited from major European
philosophers. We also find some statements which show that these philosophers were
confronted with certain insuperable difficulties while dealing with theological issues.
That is, their philosophical criteria were not satisfactory. It is obvious that these
inadequacies created an intellectual climate conducive to materialism.
|
One of the things that may appropriately be mentioned for the sake of
example is the story of the 'First Cause' in Western philosophy. Although it is somewhat a
difficult issue, we hope that our readers will show some patience.
Hegel is one of the great and famous philosophers of the world whose
greatness is certainly undeniable. There is much that is true in his works. We will first
quote a statement of this great philosopher concerning one of the most important issues of
metaphysics and then compare it with what Islamic philosophy has to say in this regard.
This statement is about the 'First Cause,' i.e. about the Necessary Being, from the
standpoint of Its being the first cause of existents. Hegel observes:
In solving the puzzle of the world of creation we should not go after
the efficient cause ('illat-e fa'ili), because, on the one hand, the mind is not satisfied
with infinite regress (tasalsul) and continues to look for the first cause. On the other
hand, when we consider the first cause, the puzzle is not solved and the mind is not
satisfied; the problem remains as to why the first cause became the first cause.
For solving the puzzle, we should find the end or the purpose and
reason for being, because if we know for what it has come into existence, or in other
words, when it is known that it is something rational, our nature is satisfied and does
not seek another cause. It is obvious that everything requires a justification by reason
while reason itself does not require any justification.
The commentators of his works have been unable to explain his intent,
but perhaps a close examination might reveal what troubled this man.
If we wish to express this matter in our own philosophical idiom, in a
manner that would accord with Hegel's viewpoint, or at least would come near it, we might
say, [the conception of] God should be accepted in a form which is directly acceptable to
the mind and not as something which the mind is constrained to accept under some
compulsion. There is a difference between a notion whose teleology (limmiyat) the mind
directly apprehendsand this apprehension is a natural oneand a notion which is
only accepted because there is a proof which negates its contradictory and compels its
acceptance. In fact, the basis of its acceptance is that one is left without an answer to
the proof negating its contradictory. On the other hand, when the contradictory of a
particular proposition is negated and proved to be false, naturally and necessarily that
proposition has to be accepted because it is not possible for both contradictories to be
false and one of them has to be necessarily accepted, considering that the falsity of one
of the two contradictories is proof of the correctness of the other.
Accepting a notion due to the falsity of its contradictory compels and
constrains the mind, without really convincing it, and there is a difference between
compelling and constraining the mind and convincing and satisfying it. Often one is
silenced by a proof while in the depth of one's consciousness there lingers a kind of
doubt and hesitation with respect to the matter proved.
This difference is observable between 'a direct proof' and reductio ad
absurdum (burhan-e khulf). At times, the mind travels naturally and consciously from the
premise and the middle term to the conclusion. The conclusion is the direct product of the
middle term, as in a deductive argument (burhan-e-limmi). In this type of proofs the mind
spontaneously deduces the conclusion from the premises, and the conclusion, to the mind,
is like a child born naturally from its parents. But in reductio ad absurdumor even
in burhan-e inni for that matterthis is not the case. In reductio ad
absurdum, the
mind accepts the conclusion as a compulsion. The state of the mind here is similar to that
of a person encountering a coercive force before which he is helpless. He accepts it
because he cannot reject it.
In these types of proofs, as one of the two possibilities is
invalidated by proof, the mind is forced into accepting the other. The other alternative
that is accepted by the mind is accepted only because its contradictory has been rejected,
and one from among a pair of contradictories has to be necessarily accepted, for it is
impossible for both contradictories to be false. Hence it accepts the other possibility
under constraint and compulsion. This acceptance of one side is due to compulsion and not
spontaneous.
Hegel wants to say that our going after the first cause and our
acceptance of it belongs to the latter category. The mind does not directly apprehend the
first cause, but accepts it to avoid infinite regress. On the other hand, it sees that
although it cannot refrain from accepting the impossibility of infinite regress, it also
cannot understand the difference between the first cause and the other causes that makes
these causes require a cause while the first cause can do without it. In his own words,
one cannot understand why the first cause became the first cause. But if we seek the
teleology and end [of being] we arrive at an end and purpose whose being an end is
essential to it and does not require any other end and purpose.
Statements similar to Hegel's with respect to the first cause have been
made by Kant and Spencer as well. Spencer says, "The problem is that, on the one
hand, human reason seeks a cause for every thing; on the other, it rejects both the
vicious circle and the infinite regress. Neither does it find an uncaused cause nor is
capable of understanding such a thing. Thus when a priest tells a child that God created
the world, the child responds by asking, 'Who created God?' "
Similar, or even more baseless, are Jean-Paul Sartre's remarks in this
regard. He, as quoted by Paul Foulquie, says concerning the first cause: It is
self-contradictory that a being be the cause of its own existence. (Paul
Foulique, L'Existentialisme,
Persian trans., p96)
Paul Foulquie, while explaining Sartre's statement, says, "The
above argument which Sartre has not elaborated is usually presented in this manner: If we
contend that we have originated our own existence, we have to believe that we existed
before our existence. This is the obvious contradiction which unravels itself. (Paul
Foulique, L'Existentialisme,
Persian trans., p96)
Let us now look at the true picture of the theory of the first cause
from the philosophical point of view. Is it as what Sartre and others saya thing
bringing itself into existence and laying the foundations of its own being, so as to imply
that a thing is its own cause and its own effect?
Or is the meaning of the first cause what Kant, Hegel and Spencer have
imagined, i.e. a being whose case involves an exception to the law of causation? That is,
although every thing requires a cause and it is impossible for it to be without a cause,
the first cause, an exception, is not such?
And is it the case that the impossibility of infinite regress, which
makes us accept the first cause, actually compels us to accept a thing's being its own
cause? Is it the case that our mind, in the process of avoiding one impossible, is forced
into accepting another? Why? If the basis is that the mind should not accept what is
impossible, then it should not accept any impossible whatsoever. Why should there be any
exception?!
In accordance with the picture presented by Sartre, the first cause,
like all other things, is in need of a cause, except that it itself fulfils its own need.
According to the conception of Kant, Hegel and Spencer, we are compelled for the sake of
avoiding infinite regress to allow an exception among things which are logically similar,
and say that all things require a cause except one, the first cause. As to the difference
between the first cause and other causes that makes all other existents depend upon a
cause while this one is an exception, the answer is that there is no logical difference.
It is only for the sake of avoiding the impossibility of infinite regress that we are
forced to assume one of them as not being in need of a cause.
In this interpretation, the first cause is not assumed to require a
cause and to meet its own need (as in Sartre's interpretation); rather, it is assumed that
the first cause does not require a cause to bring it into existence. That is, the first
cause is an exception to the law of causality. But as to why it does not require a cause,
and why is it an exception, this interpretation gives no answer.
The first interpretation is very childish. No philosopher, or even an
half-philosopher or laymen, would conceive God in this manner. Therefore, we will discuss
briefly only the second interpretation and present the correct picture while doing so.
In our view, the doubt of the likes of Kant, Hegel and Spencer
concerning the first cause derives from two basic philosophical issues, both of which have
remained unsolved in Western philosophy. Of these, the first is the issue of
fundamentality of existence (asalat al-wujud), and the second that of the criterion for
requiring a cause (manat-e ihtiyaj bi 'illat). It is not appropriate here to discuss and
explain the issue of fundamentality of existence, or the contrary doctrine of the
fundamentality of essence (asalat al-mahiyyah).
However, we shall confine ourselves to giving a brief explanation. On
the basis of the notion of fundamentality of essenceto give a very elementary and
superficial picture of it, that is, one based on the assumption that God also, like all
other existents, has an essence and an existence (which is an invalid idea even from the
viewpoint of the proponents of the theory of fundamentality of essence, because they too
consider God as pure existence)-the question arises as to why everything requires a cause
while God doesn't. Why is one being Necessary and others contingent? Is it not that all
beings are essences which come into existence?
But on the basis of the theory fundamentality of existencewhose
principal architect in regard to its philosophical demonstration and providing the proofs
is Sadr al-Muta'allihin Shirazithe pattern of thinking changes radically.
On the basis of the former theory (fundamentality of essence) our
conception of things will be that their essence is something which is intrinsically
different from existence. Existence should be given to it by another being. We name this
other being 'cause.' But in accordance with the theory of fundamentality of existence, the
real being of things is what they partake of existence. Existence is not an essence to
which another being may bestow existence. Hence if it be necessary that an external cause
bestow something, that thing would be the very being of things, which happens to be
existence itself, not something accidental and additional to the essence of things.
There is another question which arises at this point. Is it necessary
that existence as suchthat is, regardless of its form, manifestation and
planerequires to be bestowed by another being, implying that existence qua existence
is identical with being a gift and emanation [of something else with dependence, relation,
being an effect, and being posterior [to that which gives it existence], and hence is
necessarily finite? Or is there some other perspective?
The answer is that the reality of existence, despite its various planes
and manifestations, is no more than a single reality. It does not necessarily entail need
and dependence upon another thing. That is because the meaning of dependence and need with
respect to existence (in contrast to the dependence and need which were assumed earlier in
relation to essences) is that existence should itself be needy and dependent. And if the
reality of existence were need and dependence, it implies that it will be related to and
dependent upon something other than itself, while no 'other' is conceivable for existence,
because something other than existence is either non-existence or essence, which, as
presumed, is derivative (i'tibari) and a sibling of non-existence. Hence the reality of
existence qua reality of existence necessitates independence, self-sufficience, and
absence of need for and relation with something other than itself. It is also necessarily
absolute, unconditioned, and unlimited. That is, it entails the impossibility of
non-existence and negation finding a way into it. Need, want, and dependence, and
similarly finitude and mingling with non-existence, derive from another consideration,
which is different from the consideration of pure existence: these derive from
posteriority and being an effect (ma'luiyyat). That is, existence qua existence and
regardless of all other considerations necessitates self-sufficience and independence from
cause. As to the need for a causeor in other words, that a being at a particular
plane and stage should require a causethat derives from its not being the reality of
existence and its reliance upon God for coming into existence through emanation. And the
logical consequence of being an emanation is posteriority and need, or rather, it is
nothing except these.
From here we come to understand that according to the theory of
fundamentality of existence, when we focus our intellect upon the reality of existence, we
find there self-sufficience, priority, and the absence of need. In other words, the
reality of existence is equivalent to essential necessity (wujub-e dhati), and to use an
expression of Hegel's liking, the rational dimension of the reality of existence is
absence of need for a cause. Dependence upon a cause derives from a consideration
(itibar)
other than the reality of existence, and this consideration is posteriority and finitude.
In other words, the need for a cause is the same as existence at a plane posterior to the
reality of existence, and, in Hegelian terminology, the need for a cause is not the
rational dimension of existence.
This is the meaning of the statement that 'The Truthful, when they
contemplate the reality of existence and observe it sans every condition and relation
(idafah), the first thing which they discover is the Necessary Being and the First Cause.
From the Necessary Being they infer Its effects which are not pure existence, being finite
beings bearing non-being within.' This is what is meant when it is said that in this logic
there is no middle term for proving the existence of God; the Divine Being is the witness
of Its existence.
God bears witness, and those possessing knowledge and upholding
justice, and the angles, that there is no God but He. (3:18)
The proof of the sun is the sun (himself): if you require the proof, do
not avert thy face from him!
If the shadow gives an indication of him, the sun (himself) gives
spiritual life every moment.
This discloses the baselessness of the statements of those who say that
the notion of the first cause involves a contradiction because it implies that a thing is
the originator of its own existence and hence exists before coming into being.
Similarly baseless is the statement of those who say: 'Supposing that
we prove that every thing has been brought into existence by the first cause, the question
remains as to what has brought the first cause into existence; hence the first cause
remains an unjustifiable exception.
|
Hegel believed that explanation of the universe on the basis of the
first cause, irrespective of whether we consider it to be mind, matter, or God, is
impossible because the concept of the first cause itself is inexplicable. Therefore, a
different way should be found for an explanation of the universe. First we should see what
is meant by 'explanation,' he said.
Now an isolated fact is usually said to be explained when its cause has
been discovered. And if its cause cannot be ascertained, it is said to be an unexplained
fact. But we cannot explain the universe in this way. If the universe could be said to
have a cause, then either that cause is the effect of a prior cause, or it is not. Either
the chain of causes extends back in an infinite series, or there is somewhere a 'first
cause' which is not the effect of any prior cause. [f the series is infinite, then no
final and ultimate explanation is to be found. If there is a first cause, then this first
cause itself is an unexplained fact .... To explain the universe by something which is
itself an ultimate mystery is surely no explanation. (Walter Terrace
Stace, The Philosophy of Hegel, Dover
Publications, pp50-1)
Later on Hegel observes that the concept of causality not only cannot
provide an explanation of the universe but is also incapable of explaining particular
things, because explaining involves the description of the logical relationship between a
thing and something else. Whenever a thing is logically 'inferred' from something else it
is said to have been explained.
For example, when we know that angle A is equal to angle B and that
angle B is equal to angel C, we arrive at the logical conclusion that angles A and C are
equal. The mind necessarily concludes that it has to be so and it cannot be otherwise,
that it is logically impossible. Here the equality of angles A and C has been explained
with the help of two premises. These two premises are the reason or ground for the
equality of angles A and C, not its cause.
But causality does not explain a thing. Causality simply states an
existential proposition (qadiyyah wujddiyyah) and not a necessary proposition (qadiyyah
daruriyyah). This is because the concept of causality is arrived at by experience and not
through logical inference. For example, we find by experimenting that water turns into
steam due to heat and freezes due to cold. Consequently we say that heat is the cause of
vaporization and cold the cause of freezing of water. But our mind does not make a
judgment that it should be so necessarily and logically. Supposedly, if we arrived at the
opposite conclusion by experiment, finding that water freezes due to heat and turns into
steam on being exposed to cold, this would make no difference to the mind. Hence this
assumption is not something logically impossible, whereas in contrast the assumption of
inequality of angles A and C in the earlier example is a logical impossibility. Causality
does not explain that an effect should be an effect logically, and that which is a cause
should logically be a cause. Therefore, the universe should be explained through reason
and not by resorting to causes. The difference between reason and cause is that a cause is
something isolated; that is, it has an existence separate from that of its effect, whereas
a reason is not isolated and separate existence from what it explains.
For example, the equality of angles A and B, and similarly of B and C,
is the reason for the equality of angles A and C. But these reasons do not have an
existence isolated and separate from what they prove, as in the case of causes which have
an existence independent of their effects.
|
Hegel then discusses another principle, the principle of the identity
of knowing and being, or the identity of mind and reality, or the mental realm and
external reality. He is trying to remove the wall of dualism separating the mind from
external reality. In Hegel's view, the mind and external reality are not two isolated
realities alien to each other. That is, they are not two totally different entities
opposing each other. They are identical because they are but two different aspects of a
single reality. And the ground for this assertion is that the problem of how knowledge is
possible appears to be insoluble if we do not accept it. (Walter Terrace
Stace, The Philosophy of Hegel, Dover
Publications, pp71-2)
Hegel launches his philosophical project on the basis of these two
principles. The first is that reason and not cause can provide an explanation of the
universe, and the other, the identity of knowing and being. He starts with being which he
considers to be the first reason. From being he derives non-being, and from that he
arrives at 'becoming' which is a concept denoting motion. In this manner he proceeds with
his dialectic.
It is not possible for us to provide here a critique of Hegelian
philosophy and to investigate the mainspring of his errors by applying the criteria of
Islamic philosophy, which in itself would be a long and interesting account. Here it will
suffice to point out that according to the theory of fundamentality of existence
(asalat al-wujud) and with attention to the special 'Argument of the Truthful' (burhan-e
Siddiqin), Hegel's imagined dichotomy between cause and reason, between the why and
wherefore (limm-e thubiti and limm-e ithbati) vanishes. The first cause in this philosophy
is both self-sufficient and without the need of a cause, as well as self-explanatory and
requiring no ground. It is the cause as well as the ground of all things, as well as their
explainer.
For solving the problem of epistemology, too, there is no need to
resort to the identity of knowing and being as conceived by Hegel. The problem of
knowledge, which is one of the most difficult and complicated issues of philosophy, has
another solution. An elaborate discussion of these two issues has to wait for some other
occasion.
We explained that according to the doctrine of fundamentality of
existence the question as to why the first cause became the first cause becomes totally
meaningless. Now we may observe that this question also does not arise on the basis of the
doctrine of fundamentality of essence, because it arises only when we necessarily assume
that the Necessary Being possesses an essence like all other existents which is additional
to its existence.
But we are not compelled to make such an assumption. Rather we are
compelled to assume the contrary; that is, after conceding the impossibility of an
infinite regress we have no alternative except accepting the existence of the first cause,
the Necessary Being. Similarly, since the Necessary Being cannot be an entity composed of
essence and existence, we make the assent that It is pure existence and sheer ipseity
(inniyat-e sirf). Naturally there remains no room for our question.
The proof is also valid on the basis of the theory of fundamentality of
essence (aalat al-mahiyyah). Philosophers like Ibn Sina have taken the same path. If there
remains any question, it relates to another point, that if the reality of the Necessary
Being is pure existence, what is the reality of other things? Is essence the reality of
other things, existence being something derived (i'tibari) in relation to them, implying
that the realm of being is a duality? Or is it that the reality of all things is what they
partake of existence?
A correct answer to this question lies in opting for the second
alternative, which is the theory of fundamentality of existence.
Certainly the likes of Ibn Sina did not reject the fundamentality of
existence. At that time the issue of fundamentality of essence and that of existence had
not been posed among philosophers or others. Therefore this question, in the context of
Ibn Sina's exposition, is one which had not been raised during that time, and it does not
amount to an objection against his exposition. In any case, the objection raised by those
like Kant, Hegel and Spencer is not valid even aside from the fundamentality of existence.
Now we shall provide an explanation about the criterion for an effect's need for a cause.
|
The law of causality and the cause-effect relationship between things
form one of the most definite notions of human knowledge. The link and relation between
the effect and its cause is not an apparent and superficial one; it is profound and
permeates the very reality of the effect. That is, the effect, with all its being, is so
dependent upon the cause that if the cause didn't exist, it would be impossible for the
effect to come into being. All the sciences developed by man are founded upon this law. We
have proved in its appropriate place that disregarding this law is tantamount to rejecting
the presence of any order in the realm of being as well as negating every scientific,
philosophical, logical and mathematical law. Here we do not consider it necessary to
discuss this principle any further.
In this regard Islamic philosophers have posed an issue
(This was a problem posed for the first time in
Islamic Philosophy, and like many other problems it was the result of the criticisms of
the mutakallimun. The criticisms of the mutakallimun led to the emergence of certain
problems in philosophy, and in this sense philosophy is greatly indebted to them.) which in a some respects precedes the principle of causality. This
issue is: What is the criterion of the need for a cause? On this basis, in every
casefor example concerning the causal relationship between A (the cause) and B (A's
effect)two questions come to the mind:
First, why did B come into existence? The answer to this question is
that the existence of A required that B come into existence, and had A not existed, B too
would not have come into existence. Therefore, the existence of A is itself the answer to
this question. Suppose a house is destroyed by flood and someone asks, 'Why was this house
destroyed?' We reply that there was a flood.
The second question is, why does B need A and why cannot it come into
existence without it? Why is not B independent of A? Obviously, the answer to this
question is not that, 'That is because the existence of A required it.' We need to find
another answer to this question.
The reply to the first question can be given on the basis of science,
which is the product experimentation, because it is the function of science to discover
causal relationships between things. (These
remarks invoke a loose kind of speech. Science is incapable of proving the casual
relationship that is the effects needs for a cause. The most sciences can establish is an
association or succession between phenomena. We have clarified this topic fully in the
footnotes to the Usule falsafeh wa rawish e riyalism, volume 2.) Hence if we are
asked as to what is the cause of B, we reply by relying on science that the cause of B is
A.
But as to why B needs A and why it is not independent of A or any other
cause, the answer to this question lies outside the domain of science and it is not
possible to answer it by experimentation, analysis, synthesis or by distilling or grinding
in a laboratory. It is here that philosophical analysis and precise rational inference
come in. That is because the question does not relate to any concrete phenomenon, because
although the effect's need for a cause is an undeniable reality, it is not a phenomenon
isolated from the cause and the effect; that is, we do not have three external phenomena,
the cause, the effect and the effect's need for a cause. On the same basis, science, whose
function is to study phenomena, is incapable of answering this question, while philosophy,
which is capable of discovering these relationships and penetrating into the depth of
realities, is the only discipline competent to answer such questions.
From the point of view of philosophy the matter is not that B needs A
because B has never been observed empirically to come into existence without A, and
therefore B requires A and that the same is true of every effect with respect to its
cause. From the philosophical viewpoint it is impossible for an effect to be not an effect
and to be independent of the cause. The effect's dependence on the cause is inseparable
from the reality of the effect, or, rather, it is the very reality of the effect. This is
the reason why philosophy poses the issue in a general manner without discussing the
particular causal relationship between some B and A: What is the basis of causal
dependence and where does the effect's need for a cause arise? Do things need a cause just
because they are things and existents? Are thingness and existence the criteria of causal
dependence, so that every thing and every existent should be dependent upon a cause just
because of its being a thing and an existent? Or is it the case that mere thingness and
existence are not the criteria of this dependence, because, if thingness and existence
were the criteria of something they should in principle be the criteria of self-
sufficience and independence, not the criteria of need and dependence. That which can
appropriately serve as the criterion of neediness and dependence is some kind of
deficiency in thingness and existence, not thingness and existence as such and ontic
perfection.
Islamic philosophers, as well as the theologians
(mutakallimun), who
were the first ones to have started this debate, never considered thingness and existence
per se as the criteria of neediness and dependence because that would imply that an
existent needs a cause merely because it is existent. Rather, they were definite that
there is another aspect of things deriving from their aspect of deficiency and nonbeing
wherein lie the roots of this neediness and dependence. Altogether three theories have
been advanced in this regard.
|
The mutakallimun considered the criterion of neediness and dependence
of effects upon causes and their lack of independence to be ,hududth, that is, their
previous non-existence. They considered the absence of a thing's need for a cause to lie
in its being eternal (qidam). They said that if the existence of a being was preceded by
non-existence ('adam), or if, in other words, a thing did not exist at a time and came
into existence at another time such an existent, on the basis that it was non-existent
earlier and came into being later, needs a cause to bring it into existence, and its
existence will depend upon something other than itself. But if there is a being which is
eternal and there was never a time that it did not exist, such a being will be independent
and without the need for a cause; it would not be dependent upon something else by any
means. The mutakallimun held that the causal relationship between two things, for example,
A in relation to B, is that A brings B into existence from a state of non-existence, and
this is only possible where B's existence is preceded by non-existence. But if B is
assumed to be eternal and there was never a time that it did not exist, then the causality
of A with respect to it makes no sense.
In fact, the mutakallimun identified the [ontic] deficiency that is the
basis of neediness and dependence of things upon something else to lie in previous
non-existence, that is, in the temporal precedence of non-existence over existence. And
they considered the source of perfection, self-sufficience and absence of dependence upon
something else to be eternity or non- precedence by non-existence. Therefore, from the
point of view of the mutakallimun, a being is either deficient, needy, preceded by
non-existence (hadith) and dependent upon another, or it is perfect, self-sufficient,
eternal and not dependent upon anything.
These philosophers raised basic objections against the theory of the
mutakallimun wherein huduth and previous non-existence were considered the criteria of
ontic deficiency, need and dependence upon something else. However, this is not the place
to mention their objections. They said that though it is true that everything which is
hadith (preceded by non-existence) needs a cause, but the criterion for the hadith's need
for a cause is not its huduth but something else. They also said that eternity is in no
way the criterion of self-sufficience, perfection and absence of dependence. The
philosophers claimed that the criterion of ontic deficiency and perfection, and of need
and self-sufficience, should be sought in the essence and quiddity (mahiyyah) of beings,
not in previous non-existence, huduth, or eternal existence, qidam.
Things in their essence (dhat), from the point of view of being, are of
two kindsor at least can be assumed to be of two kinds. The first is the case where
their being is their actual essence, that is, they do not have any essence (mahiyyah)
apart from their existence. In other words their essence and their existence are one and
the same. The second case is where the essence of a thing is something distinct from its
existence and nonexistence. We call the first kind necessary being (wajib al-wujud), and
the second, contingent being (mumkin al-wujud). The Necessary Being, from the standpoint
of being existence itselfit being senseless for a thing to be devoid of itself, and
impossible for it not to exist while being existence itselfis not in need of a
cause, because causality implies that the cause brings the being of the effect into
existence, and when the essence (dhat) of a thing is actual existence and there is no
vacuum in it in this regard, the need for a cause does not exist. But a contingent being,
from the viewpoint that it is neither existent nor non-existent in itself, being equally
indifferent with respect to both the sides and having a vacuum in relation to both of
them, needs something else to fill this vacuum, and that something is the cause. The
existence of the cause fills that vacuum with existence, and that which is
contingent-existent-in-itself (mumkin al-wujud bi al-dhat) becomes
necessarily-existence-through-another (wajib al-wujdd bi al-ghayr). The nonexistence of a
cause fills that vacuum with non-existence and a contingent-existent-in-itself becomes
impossible due to the absence of its cause (mumtani' al-wu jad bi al-ghayr).
The philosophers call this [ontic] vacuum "essential
contingency" (imkan dhati) and consider it to be the criterion for requiring a cause.
Similarly, they name [ontic] plenitude "essential necessity" (wujub
dhati).
In fact, from the point of view of philosophers, the essential
deficiency which makes existents needy, deficient, and dependent upon something else is
that essential vacuity (khala' dhati), and the essential perfection (kamal dhati) which is
the source of perfection of an existent and makes it needless with respect to dependence
upon another is that 'essential plenitude' (mala' dhati), that is the identity of essence
(dhat) and existence.
As these philosophers consider the root and criterion of dependence to
be essential vacuity and not previous non-existence, if there were to exists a being in
the world which is eternal, there being no time that it did not exist and without ever
being preceded by non-existence, it would still be a contingent existent (mumkin
al-wujud), that is, its essence is not identical with its existence and it has a vacuity
of existence at the plane of its essence.Such a being is an effect, a creature, and
dependent upon another despite being eternal and everlasting. The philosophers believe
that such existents do exist and they name them 'uql-e qahirah (the Supreme Intellects).
Sadr al-Muta'allihin conceded that every hadith existent depends upon
something else. He also accepted that every contingent being is in need of a cause. He
considered valid the objections raised by the philosophers against the theologians, and
agreed with the philosophers that there is nothing to prevent an existent from being
temporally eternal, existing since preeternity and everlasting, while being dependent, a
creature and an effect. Similarly he endorsed the view of the philosophers that the
criterion of neediness and dependence should be sought within things themselves and not in
their previous non-existence. However, he proved that in the same way that huduth cannot
be the criterion of neediness, so also essential contingency (imkan dhati), or in our
words 'essential vacuity,' too, cannot be the criterion of dependence and neediness
because essential contingency is an attribute of essence, and it is essence which is said
to be essentially indifferent to being and non-being and something hollow and empty,
requiring something else to fill it. But considering that essence is derivative
(istibari)
and not fundamental, it lies outside the realm of neediness and self-sufficience causing
and being caused, efficiency and receptivity. Rather essence lies outside the domain of
existence and non-existence. Essential contingency (imkan mahuwi) cannot be the principal
basis of this neediness. All these characteristics such as existence and non-existence,
causing and being caused, neediness and self-sufficience, can be attributed to essence,
but only accidentally (bi al-'arad), metaphorically, and secondarily, that is following
existence, from which essence is derived and abstracted. Therefore, the real basis of
intrinsic neediness and intrinsic self-sufficience should be sought in existence itself.
In the same way that Sadr al Muta'allihin proved the fundamentality of existence
(asalat al-wujud), he also proved the gradation of existence, that is the hierarchy of different
planes of existence. Accordingly, in the same way as self-sufficience does not lie outside
the reality of existence, similarly neediness too is not external to the reality of
existence, and in the same way as perfection is not something extraneous to the reality of
existence but is identical with it, so also deficiency is not external to it. It is the
reality of existence which receives perfection and deficiency, plenitude and poverty,
self-sufficience and neediness, intensity and weakness, necessity and contingency,
infinitude and finitude or is rather identical with them. The reality of existence in its
purity and at the plane of its own essence is equivalent to perfection, self-sufficience,
independence, intensity, necessity and infinitude, while deficiency, need, dependence,
contingency, and the like are posterior to the plane of the essence and derive from being
an effect (ma'luliyyat) with its implied deficiency.
From Sadr al-Muta'allihin's point of view, the notion of essential
vacuity of essence in respect of existence and the need for something else to fill this
vacuum is correct only on the basis of fundamentality of essence, not on the basis of
fundamentality of existence. On the basis of fundamentality of existence, attributing need
and essential vacuity to essence and the notion that something else called 'cause' is
required to fill this vacuum, are only correct as a loose philosophical metaphor. Causing
('illiyyat) and being caused (ma'luliyyat), as well as self-sufficience and need, all
pertain to something which is concrete and real, and that is existence. The roots of an
existent's dependence on another existent lie in its essential deficiency and its
essential finitude.
In contrast to the opinion of the theologians and the vast majority of
philosophers, according to Sadr al-Muta'allihin's view, need, the needy, and the criterion
of neediness are not different things; need, the needy, and the criterion of neediness,
all the three are a single thing. Certain planes of existence are identical with actual
need with respect to another plane by virtue of their essential deficiency and essential
posteriority (ta'akhkhur dhati) to the principal source of existence, .
Sadr al-Muta'allihin also follows the classical approach of such
philosophers as Ibn Sina while discussing the issue of criterion for the need of a cause,
but elsewhere he expresses his own opinion on this issue, which is a definite and
inevitable result of the principles he has propounded. As he has dealt with the issue in
the classical manner by adopting the approach of his predecessors, later scholars and the
followers of his school, like the late Hajji Sabzawari, have imagined that Sadr
al-Muta'allihin does not have a distinct opinion of his own on this issue. We have for the
first time highlighted this fact in the footnotes of Usul-e falsafeh wa rawish-e riyallsm
('The Principles and Method of the Philosophy of Realism') and have presented it for the
benefit of others.
In any case, that which is definite in accordance with the views of all
the schools is that the roots of dependence upon a cause do not lie simply in being a
thing or being an existent. Things, just because they have existence, do not require a
cause. Existence, more than being indicative of dependence, is indicative of
self-sufficience.
From what we have said two facts come to light:
-
That which is often said that 'Every thing, or every existent,
requires a cause,' is not only incorrect but also a grave error. The correct thing to say
is that 'Every deficient being is in need of a cause.' As we have seen, the different
schools which have discussed this topic differ in their determination of the deficiency
which makes the criterion for dependence on a cause, but they concur that every deficient
thing requires a cause, not every thing whether it is deficient or perfect.
-
Our conception of the First Cause has now become clear. It
became evident that the First Cause, which is the same as the eternal, perfect, infinite
Essence (dhat) of the Necessary Being, is the first cause because existence itself is Its
essence, and existence in itself is perfect, not deficient, and limitless, not limited,
thus ruling out any dependence upon a cause. The meaning of the First Cause is neither
that it is its own causein the sense that it lays the foundation of its own
existence and brings itself into beingnor that the First Cause does not differ from
all other existents with regard to the need for a cause and that it is an exception to the
law of causality.
Here it is possible that a doubt may arise in the minds of those who
are not trained in these issues, that although it is correct that the First Cause, because
of its being eternal, perfect, infinite and necessarily existent, is free from all forms
of dependence, while all other things on account of their not possessing these qualities
are dependent and in need, but why did the First Cause become the first cause? That is,
why did only the First Cause, from among all existents, become eternal (qadim), perfect,
infinite and necessarily existent? Why didn't It become hadith and deficient? Why didn't
another existent, which is presently deficient and dependent, not take the place of the
Necessary Being?
In view of the explanation provided, the answer to this question is
obvious. It has been presumed in this question that it was possible for the Necessary
Being not be a necessary being and that it was through the interference of a cause that It
became a necessary and not a contingent being. It has also been assumed that it is
possible for a contingent being not to be a contingent being, and that it became such due
to the intervention of some cause. In other words, it was possible for an essentially
perfect and infinite being to be deficient and finite, and for a deficient and finite
being to be essentially perfect and infinite, and it was due to the intervention of some
factor that one became essentially perfect and infinite while the other became essentially
deficient and finite. Yes, this is the basis of the question.
The questioner is oblivious of the fact that the plane of existence of
each existent is the essence (dhat) of that existent, in just the same manner as the plane
of each number is the actual essence of that number. Therefore, if an existent becomes
independent of a cause as a result of essential self- sufficience and essential
perfection, the consequence is that no cause can interfere with it in any manner, no cause
has brought it into existence, and no cause has placed it at the plane at which it
subsists. The question as to why the First Cause became the first causewhich is
considered unanswerable in Western philosophyis actually a meaningless question. For
the First Cause, Its existence is Its reality and Its very essence (dhat), and being the
First Cause is also identical with Its essence, and in both capacities it has no need of a
cause.
This question is just like saying, 'Why is the number one, one? Why
didn't it not become two? Why did two become number two and not one, and why it didn't
take the place of one?' Since we have discussed the matter that the plane of existence of
each existent is actually the very essence of that existent in greater detail in our book
'Adl-e Ilahi ('Divine Justice'), we shall refrain from repeating it here.
As a conclusion to this part of the discussion it would be appropriate
to cite the remarks of Bertrand Russell, a contemporary philosopher, about the First Cause
for ascertaining the character of his philosophical views concerning this profound issue.
Russell has a small book by the name Why I am not a Christian. In it he
does not simply limit his criticism to Christianity, but rather criticizes religious ideas
in general, and the idea of God in particular, which is accepted even by some
non-religious persons.
Among the things he objects to in that book is 'the First Cause
argument.' In order to know how Mr. Russell, this great Western philosopher whose fame has
spread everywhere, has conceived these issues in his mind we shall quote him here. He
says:
It is maintained that everything we see in this world has a cause, and
as you go back in the chain of causes further and further you must come to a First Cause,
and to that First Cause you give the name of God.
Then Russell goes on to refute the argument in these words:
I may say that when I was a young man and was debating these questions
very seriously in my mind, I for a long time accepted the argument of the First Cause,
until one day, at the age of eighteen, I read John Stuart Mill's Autobiography, and I
there found this sentence: 'My father taught me that the question, "Who made
me?" cannot be answered, since it immediately suggests the further question,
"Who made God?" ' That very simple sentence showed me, as I still think, the
fallacy in the argument of the First Cause. If everything must have a cause, then God must
have a cause. If there can be anything without a cause, it may just as well be the world
as God, so that there cannot be any validity in that argument.
Our previous observations highlight the fallacy in Russell's argument.
The argument is not about whether everything must have a cause or if it is possible for a
being to exist without a cause as an exception, that if it is possible for one thing to
exist without a cause, what difference would it make whether it is God or the universe.
The issue involved is that [the thingness of] every thing and [the
existence of] all that exists is neither the criterion of dependence upon a cause nor that
of non-dependence in respect of its being something and having some kind of existence, so
that the question may arise as to what difference is there among these things in this
respect. The issue at hand is that among things and existents there exists an entity and a
being which is pure existence and absolute perfection, and every perfection derives from
it and is directed towards it, and it, being identical with existence, is in no need of a
causeas against things which have a borrowed existenceand such a being neither
lacks existence nor any of its perfections for it to either seek them, or hasten to
acquire them, nor does it lose them.
On the other hand, we live in a world in which everything has a
transient nature and is in search of something which it lacks, and everything at another
time loses what it presently possesses. We live in a world in which everything is subject
to decline, annihilation, change and transformation, and all the signs of poverty, need,
dependence, indebtedness and having a borrowed existence are evident on the face of every
thing. Therefore, such a world cannot be the First Cause and the Necessary Being. And this
is the Abrahamic argument mentioned in the Noble Qur'an:
So We were showing Abraham the kingdom
of the heavens and earth, that he might be of those having sure faith. When night
outspread over him he saw a star and said, 'This is my Lord.' But when it set he said, 'I
love not the setters.' When he saw the moon rising, he said, 'This is my Lord.' But when
it set he said, 'If my Lord does not guide me I shall surely be of the people gone
astray.' When he saw the sun rising, he said, 'This is my Lord; this is greater!' But when
it set he said, 'O my people, surely I am quit of that you associate. I have turned my
face to Him who originated the heavens and the earth, a man of pure faith; I am not of the
idolaters.' (Al-Qur'an 6:75-79)
The summary of the argument is that, in consonance with primordial
nature and self-evident judgement of the intellect, he considers himself a being that is
servile and subject to and sustained [by something else], and dedicates himself to the
search of his lord and sustainer. The star, the moon, and the sunwhich are the most
luminous existents and which the people of Abraham's time considered as power that
regulated and ruled the worldby turns capture his attention, but after a moment's
contemplation the signs of subjugation, subjection, and being sustained by something else
become evident in them as well as other existents in the world of nature. Thereat Abraham
sets everything aside and turns his heart towards the mighty power which is the absolute
sustainer and absolutely supreme, and in which there is no sign of subjugation,
subjection, huduth, annihilation, need and poverty. From the presence of need and
annihilation, transience and decline, dependence and subjection, he discovers the
existence of that subjugating power and perfection.
|
Among the various issues which in my opinion have had a great impact on
materialistic tendencies is the false notion that there is a contradiction between the
principle of creation on the one hand and the theory of evolution, especially the
evolution of living organisms, on the other. In other words, the fallacy is that creation
amounts to instantaneous coming into existence of things, while evolution means that
things do not have a creator.
As history indicates, the idea existed, especially in the Western
world, that the implication of the universe being created by God is that all things should
be unvarying and fixed, and that there should be no change in the universe, especially in
the principles of the universe, that is, the species. Hence evolution is impossible,
especially where it relates to the essence and necessitates a change in the essence of a
thing and a mutation of its species. On the other hand, we observe that with the
development of the sciences the notion that things, especially living creatures, show an
ascending evolutionary movement becomes ever more confirmed and established. The
conclusion that is drawn from these two premises is that the sciences, especially
biological sciences, are moving in an anti-theistic direction.
As we know, the views of Lamarck and Darwin, especially those of the
latter, raised a storm in Europe. Although Darwin was himself a believer in God and
religion, and as related, sat the time of his death he held the Bible pressed to his
chest,' and repeatedly in his writings declared his faith in God, his ideas were
introduced as being totally anti-God.
Someone might say that evolutionism in general (especially Darwinism,
in view of the hypothesis that the origin of man is from the ape, which was later
abandoned) was considered anti-God because it went against the contents of the holy
scriptures. In religious scriptures the creation of man has been usually traced back to a
single human being named Adam, and this apparently implies that he was directly created
from dust. Accordingly, it was both correct and proper that Darwin and the Darwinists, or
rather all the proponents of evolution, be branded as anti-God, because in no way is it
possible to reconcile faith in religion with belief in the theory of evolution. There is,
therefore, no alternative to accepting one from among these two and rejecting the other.
The reply to this is that, firstly, what the sciences have opined in
this regard are hypotheses which are either constantly changing, modified, or even
abandoned and replaced by other hypotheses. On the basis of such hypotheses, it is neither
possible to reject some idea stated explicitly and without any room for interpretation in
a divine scripture, nor is it possible to consider such hypotheses a proof of the
baselessness of religion as such and the baselessness of religion as a proof for the
non-existence of God.
Secondly, scientific opinion has moved in a direction which shows that
the basic changes occurring in living creatures, especially at stages where their species
changes and their essence undergoes mutation, are in the form of a leap, swift and sudden.
Therefore, the concept of very gradual, intangible and cumulative changes is no longer
relevant. When science considers it possible for an infant to cover a distance of hundred
years in a single night, what evidence is there that it cannot cover the distance of
hundreds of million years in forty nights? Even if that which has been mentioned in
religious texts be presumed to imply explicitly the creation of the first man directly
from dust, it has been expressed in a manner that shows that it involved some kind of
action and reaction in nature. It is stated in religious texts that Adam's clay was formed
in forty days. Who knows, perhaps all the stages which the first living cell had to cover
in the natural course in billions of years for it to eventually give rise to a human
being, may have been covered in forty days by Adam's clay in extraordinary conditions
which the hand of Divine power had brought about, in the same way as the human ovum, in a
period of nine months in the womb, is said to cover all the stages the animal predecessors
of man took billions of years to cover.
Thirdly, suppose that what the sciences say in this regard is more than
a mere hypothesis and is a confirmed scientific fact, that it is not possible to create
natural conditions so that matter may swiftly and speedily cover the stages which it
covers slowly under a different set of conditions, and that it is a scientifically
confirmed fact that man had animal ancestors. In the light of these assumptions, are the
relevant religious texts such that they cannot be interpreted accordingly? If we
specifically take the Noble Qur'an as the criterion, we find that the Qur'an has narrated
the story of Adam in a symbolic manner. I do not mean to say that the Adam mentioned in
the Qur'an is not a person's name but a symbol representing the human species. I don't
mean to say that. To be certain the first Man (Adam) was an individual and a person having
concrete existence. What I mean is that the Qur'an has narrated the story of Adam in a
symbolic way from the point of view of his stay in heaven, his seduction by Satan, greed,
and jealousy, his expulsion from heaven, his penitence, and so on. The conclusion the
Qur'an derives from this story is not from the standpoint of the wonderful creation of
Adam and it does not play any role in drawing any theological conclusion. Rather, the
Qur'an narrates the story of Adam solely from the point of view of man's spiritual station
and from the viewpoint of certain ethical issues. It is fully possible for a person who
believes in God and the Qur'an to retain his faith in God and the Qur'an while
interpreting the story of Adam's creation in some manner. Today, we know religious persons
who have faith in God, the Prophet (s) and the Qur'an, and who interpret the story of
Adam's creation in a manner consonant with the modern sciences. No one has claimed that
these views contradict with faith in the Qur'an. I myself, while studying these views in
books on this subject, find in them many points worthy of attention and reflection,
although I am not totally convinced about them.
However, to consider such issues a pretext for rejecting the Qur'an and
religion is far from scientific justice, to say nothing of using them as an excuse for
negating belief in God.
Fourthly, suppose we accept that the literal meanings of religious
texts are not susceptible to an alternative interpretation and that man's descent from
animals is scientifically definite. At the most it would mean that one will lose faith in
religious scriptures. But why should one lose faith in God? Firstly, it is possible that
new religions may emerge which do not subscribe to the idea of man's direct creation from
dust as explicitly as the Torah. Secondly, does the rejection of a single, some, or all
religions logically imply the rejection of belief in God? There have always been
individuals who have had faith in God without adhering to any religion.
From all that we have said it is known that the assumed contradiction
between the contents of religious texts and the theory of evolution cannot be considered a
reason for inclining towards materialism; the reason must be something else. The fact is
that the European materialists imagined the hypothesis of evolution to be rationally and
logically incompatible with the issue of God, irrespective of its compatibility with
religion. Accordingly, they proclaimed that belief in God is negated by acceptance of the
theory of evolution.
Let us now examine this argument, to see whether there is any rational
and logical contradiction between these two issues, or if the inadequacy of the concepts
of European philosophy is responsible for an imagined contradiction. Whatever it may be,
we need to examine the approach taken by the materialists in taking this contradiction for
granted.
We can explain their statements in two ways. Firstly, in the sense that
the theists are deprived of their most important argument with the emergence of the theory
of evolution. A major argument of the theists for proving the existence of an omniscient
and wise creator was the presence of a perfect order of existents. This perfect order is
more evident in the plant and animal kingdoms. If the creation of plants and animals had
been instantaneous, the argument based on the perfect order of existents would have been
correct, because it was not rationally acceptable that a being could come into existence
instantaneously and all of a sudden without any intelligent plan, especially where it
possesses such structures which show that its formation, design, and organism has been
created with a planned purpose. But if the creation of the existents was gradual and
extended in time, that is, if it has taken place in the course of hundreds of millions of
years and the structure of existents has acquired the present form little by little with
the passing of centuries and generations, there is no obstacle to regarding these
intricate systems as entirely unplanned. That is, no intelligent power has supervised it
and only coincidences and forced conformity with the environment have been the cause of
these systems and organisms.
Therefore, with the acceptance and confirmation of mutation the main
argument of the theists is taken away from them, and this by itself is sufficient to tilt
the balance in favour of the materialists and make a group incline towards that side.
But this interpretation is in itself incorrect. If such views are
presented before a vigorous theistic school of thought it will immediately reply that,
firstly, it is a mistake to consider the perfection of design as the only argument for the
existence of God, and to mention it as the main argument is indeed an exaggeration.
Secondly, the whole order of creation is not limited to the structure of animal organs for
it to be said that the gradual evolution of species is enough to explain their accidental
existence. Thirdly, the important and also the principal reply to this criticism is that
the gradual emergence of and accidental changes occurring in the structure of plants and
animals are not at all sufficient for explaining the precise systems of their bodies.
Accidental changes can be considered sufficient only when we presume
that there occurs a change in the body of a living creature as a result of an accident or
an aimless act, or an act meant for some purpose other than the consequence produced; for
instance, when a web is formed accidentally on a duck's feet and proves helpful in
swimming and is transferred to later generations as a result of heredity.
But, firstly, from the viewpoint of heredity, the transfer of acquired
and individual characteristics, especially acquired characteristics, is highly improbable
or rather ruled out. Secondly, all organs and members of the body are not like the web of
a duck's foot. Generally, every part is itself a part of an elaborate and complicated
system, such as those relating to digestion, respiration, vision, hearing, and so on. Each
of these systems is an organized and interlinked apparatus in which the related function
and characteristic is not achieved unless all its parts come into existence. For example,
the membranes of the eye are not such that each of them be assumed to perform a separate
function of the body and as having come into existence gradually in millions of years.
Rather the eye, along with all its membranes, fluids, nerves and muscles with their
astonishing number, variety, organization and formation performs a single function. It is
not admissible that accidental changes, even in billions of years, would gradually give
rise to the ocular or auricular system.
The theory of evolution more than anything points towards the role of
an intelligent and guiding force in the being of living creatures and demonstrates the
principle of teleology.
Darwin himself propounded the principle of adaptation to environment in
such terms that he was told that he spoke of it as if it were a metaphysical principle. It
is a reality that the capacity of living organisms to adapt to the environment, which is a
very mysterious and astonishing power, is something metaphysical; that is, it is subject
to a kind of guidance and consciousness of purpose, and is in no way a blind and aimless
power.
The principle of evolution implies the presence of an unseen regulating
power in the universe no less than any other theory. The reason that Darwin and many other
later biologists are theists and religious persons is this that they have not considered
the principles and laws of naturesuch as the principles of struggle for survival,
heredity, selection of the fittest, and adaptation to the environment (if interpreted
solely as an ordinary blind natural reaction to the environment)by any means
sufficient for explaining the emergence of living organisms. Of course, we do not say that
they did not consider them necessary and reverted to the theory of instantaneous creation
of living organisms. All that we are saying is that they did not consider them sufficient.
Actually, the reason why the theory of evolution was considered
contradictory to the famous theist argument for the existence of God based upon perfect
design was doubtlessly the weakness of the systems of philosophy and metaphysics. Instead
of utilizing the emergence of the theory of evolution to the advantage of the theist
school, they considered it as antithetical to theist thought, because they imagined that
only an instantaneously created universe needed a cause and creator, and if the universe
or any species were to come into existence gradually, the gradual natural factors were
sufficient to explain their existence. Such assumptions indicate the weakness of the
Western systems of philosophic thought.
Apart from the assumption that the theory of evolution weakens the
argument by design and perfection of creation, there existed another reason why the
evolutionary school was considered antithetical to theism, thus assisting the spread of
materialism. This was the supposition that if there were a God, things must have come into
existence according to a prior plan; that is, the existence of things should have been
anticipated in God's knowledge and then created by His irresistible will.
The presence of a prior plan implies the total absence of chance,
because chance contradicts foreknowledge, being something unexpected and unpredictable.
But we know that chance plays an extraordinary important and effective role in the
creation of the universe. Even if we suppose that chance is not sufficient for the initial
existence of things, we cannot deny its existence and effective role in the process of
creation For example, the earth, which is the cradle of living organisms, was a fragment
which came into existence due to a chance, for instance, due to the sun's nearing a big
spherical body and coming under its gravitational pull. Had there existed a prior plan, or
a fate predetermined since eternity, chance would have no role. The conclusion is that if
God exists things should come into existence in a manner preplanned and foreknown in His
eternal knowledge, and had things been foreknown in God's eternal knowledge there would be
no chance. And since chance has an effective role in creation, the creation of things was
unpredictable, and since it was unpredictable, there is no God.
Apart from this, if things came into existence due to the eternal
Divine will, it was necessary for them to do so instantaneously at one stroke, because
God's will is absolute, irresistible and unconditional. The implication of God's absolute,
irresistible and unconditional will is that everything He intends to create comes into
existence without a moment's delay. Hence it is mentioned in religious texts that God's
command is such that when He wills something He says, 'Be', and it comes into existence
immediately. Therefore, if the world and things existing in it have come into existence by
God's will, it follows that the world must come into existence from the very beginning in
whatever form or state it would eventually assume.
The conclusion derived from these two pointsone of which relates
to God's eternal knowledge and the other to the Divine willis that if God exists,
there exist both an eternal Divine knowledge and an eternal will, and eternal knowledge
and eternal will require that things come into existence instantaneously.
The reply is that neither God's eternal knowledge nor His eternal will
require that things come into existence instantaneously. Further, neither the theists the
world over nor the religious texts have posed the issue in this manner.
It is mentioned in religious texts that God created the universe in six
days. Regardless of whatever may be implied by 'six days,' be it six periods, or six days
of God, each of which is equal to a thousand years, or six ordinary days amounting to 144
hours, that which is understood from this statement is gradualness. The theists have never
said that the eternal knowledge of God and His absolute will necessitate that the heavens
were created in a single moment and instantaneously. The scriptures say that they were
created gradually during a certain period of time.
And the Noble Qur'an also states very explicitly the gradual
development of the foetus in the womb and considers it as a pointer to the knowledge of
God. Nobody has ever said that the necessary implication of God's eternal knowledge and
willwhich is such that when it relates to a certain thing and He says, 'Be,' the
thing comes into beingis that the foetus develops momentarily. This was from the
viewpoint of the scriptures.
From the point of view of philosophy, the claim that God's eternal
knowledge implies that chance does not play any effective role whatsoever, requires a bit
of explanation.
From the philosophic viewpoint, fortuity and accident, or in other
words chance, does not exist at all, and that which men calls chance is not chance in
reality and does not essentially differ in the least from all other causes and effects,
prerequisites and consequences.
The word 'chance' is used in two different senses. The first sense is
where something comes into being without any efficient cause, that is, a thing that
supposedly did not exist comes into existence without the interference of any factor. This
kind of chance is rejected by all schools of thought irrespective of their being theists
or materialists, because even the materialists do not accept such a hypothesis about the
origin of the universe. This kind of chance is also not related to the topic of our
present discussion, because even those who claim that organic changes in animals are due
to chance factors do not imply this kind of chance.
The other sense in which this word is used is where a consequence
follows from conditions which are not its prerequisite, or when conditions give rise to a
consequence which does not follow from them. For example, if you get into a car in Tehran
and drive on the Tehran-Qum highway you will reach Qum after two or three hours. You never
say that I drove on this highway and accidentally reached Qum, because the natural outcome
of this journey is your reaching Qum. Now suppose you have an old friend whom you have not
seen for years. While travelling to Qum you are neither thinking about him nor looking
around for him, but as soon as you reach 'Aliabad on the Tehran-Qum highway, you get off
the car to relax for a while at an inn. Finding an empty chair at a table, all of a sudden
you find your friend whom you had not seen for twenty years. You come to know that he was
living in Shiraz and had come to Tehran, that he too had stopped there to relax for a
while when he saw you. Here each of you will say, 'We met by chance on the
Tehran-Qum
highway.' The reason why both of you consider this meeting accidental is that in the
general course of nature travelling between Tehran and Qum does not necessarily result in
such a meeting. Were it necessary, it would mean that such a meeting should occur whenever
you travel from Tehran to Qum whatever the circumstances, while it is not so. This event
took place only during this particular journey which took place at a particular time under
its particular circumstances. That is why this meeting was not foreseeable for you or your
friend or anyone in your place, and neither you nor your friend would have been able to
include this meeting in his plans while planning his journey. Things which can be foreseen
and included in an itinerary are those which occur in the natural course of journey
between Tehran and Qum.
But if you turn your attention from the general character of the
journey from Tehran to Qum and focus your attention on this particular journey which was
made at a particular time under particular conditions, and if you take it into
consideration with its accompanying circumstances and conditions and other accompanying
events, you will find that your meeting your friend at that specific point and at that
moment was not at all accidental; rather it was necessary, natural and inevitable
consequence of your journey towards Qum, and was also totally predictable for someone who
was aware of all the movements and circumstances of both of you.
This meeting is accidental in the eyes of someone who takes into view
the general nature of the journey from Tehran to Qum. Obviously this journey has a set of
general implications, and that which lies outside them, from the point of view of its
general nature, will be considered chance. But that which exists is not just the general
nature; that which exists is that general nature along with a set of condition, and the
notion of chance vanishes on taking into consideration these conditions and additional
facts .
Here we give another example to further elucidate how accident and
chance are subjective in nature; that is, it is an accident or chance from the viewpoint
of a person who is ignorant of the causes, whereas from the standpoint of one who has
knowledge of the causes involved there is no chance or accident.
Imagine two persons employed in a certain institution and who receive
their instructions from a single source. One of them, Mr. A, is employed in Khurasan and
the other, Mr. B, works at Isfahan. Instructions are received from the headquarters
ordering Mr. A to leave on a certain date for a disaster-stricken area to perform some
specific task, and soon afterwards instructions are received by Mr. B ordering him to go
on the same day to the same place for performing another task. Obviously Mr. A and Mr. B
meet each other at that place and their meeting is accidental for each of them. Both of
them will say that they met each other accidentally on a certain day and at a certain
place. Each of them separately views the nature of his task and finds that this meeting
was not a necessary consequence of his task and that it was not predictable for either of
them. But from the viewpoint of the headquarters, which ordered both of these apparently
separate and unrelated assignments that were carried out under its instructions, this
meeting was not at all accidental. For the headquarters, which determined the courses of
the two journeys from Isfahan and Mashad to that point and arranged both of them in such a
manner that the two individuals reached that point on a specific date, their meeting and
coming together was very natural and inevitable. The headquarters cannot say that it sent
these two and they accidentally met each other at a certain place. Therefore, accident and
chance are relative; it is an accident in relation to one who is unaware of the
happenings, whereas for one who knows the details of events and has a complete knowledge
of the circumstances and conditions there is no accident or chance involved. This is why
they say: that which is called 'chance' is such only in relation to one who is ignorant of
the causes, not for one who has complete knowledge of the events.
From this we come to know that for God, the Exalted, and in fact from
the viewpoint of reality and what actually takes place, there is no question of accident
or chance. Hence, to say that 'if we accept God we must also accept that the events in the
universe occur in accordance with a plan and are therefore predictable and involve no
accident or chance, whereas the sciences believe in an effective and important role of
chance and accident,' is something baseless.
The accidents are such with reference to us who are ignorant of the
totality of causes, not with reference to God, who is the Creator and Originator of every
thing and encompasses all causes, conditions, and circumstances.
Now something regarding [God's] eternal will.
This objection is weaker than the first one. Strangely enough, has been
imagined that God's absolute and eternal will implies that all existents come into being
instantaneously! What a big blunder! The implication of God's absolute will is that
everything should come into existence in the manner He desires and in the form He intends
without facing any opposition and obstacle, that there be no gap between His will and the
thing willed, not that everything which He desires should come into existence in an
instantaneous manner.
To explain, if we, who have a deficient and finite will, will
something, we have to rely upon things other than our own will, and unless we obtain those
means our will by itself can achieve nothing. Also we need to remove certain obstacles,
because our will cannot be realized with their presence. But since God's will encompasses
all things and everything is the result of His will, the means and hindrances too are the
creation of His will. Thus at the plane where His will prevails there exists nothing by
way of a precondition, means, or obstacle: all conditions, means, obstacles and their
absence are subservient and subject to His will. Therefore, that which He wills exists in
the manner willed by Him, without the least delay. If the existence of a thing depends
upon the fulfillment of certain conditions, it is proper to say from the viewpoint of that
thing that it depends on these conditions, but it is not correct to say about God's will
that it depends upon certain conditions. That is, the execution of Divine will is not
dependent upon anything; rather it is Divine will which ordains the thing with those
conditions and it comes into existence in the manner willed by Him without any departure.
Thus the meaning of God's possessing an absolute will is that whatever
He wills takes place in the manner He wills, without His will depending upon anything
beyond Himself for its execution. Therefore, if He wills a thing's existence to be
instantaneous that thing comes into being instantaneously. But if He wills that a thing's
existence be gradual it comes into being gradually. It depends upon the mode of the
thing's existence and the manner in which God has willed its existence.
If Divine will and wisdom so ordain that living creatures should come
into existence gradually in a span of billions of years, they will naturally come into
existence in this manner. Therefore, it is wrong to say that God's absolute will requires
that everything come into existence instantaneously. The logical implication of the
absolute Divine will is that everything comes into existence in the manner decreed by Him,
instantaneously or gradually, without depending upon anything beyond the Divine will.
Apart from this, the philosophers have proved that things having a
gradual character have an existence that can only be gradual; it is impossible for them to
have any other kind of existence, either static or instantaneous. Hence the receptivity
(qabiliiyyah) of the receiver (qabil) also necessitates gradualness.
Sadr al-Muta'allihin has proved that there is a kind of motion in the
world called 'substantial motion' (harkat jawhariyyah). According to the theory of
substantial motion there is nothing static in nature nor can possibly be. All things
existing in nature have a gradual existence and it cannot be otherwise. This philosopher,
who is also a divine 'arif (gnostic), never thought that there might be people in the
future who would imagine that the instantaneous creation of all things was implied by
God's eternal knowledge or will.
A few years ago I wrote an article "Monotheism and Evolution"
("Tawhid wa Takamul") for the monthly Maktab-e Tashayy'u in which I have
discussed the errors in the approach of Western philosophers in considering theism to be
incompatible with the concept of evolution.
|
| |
|